CHAPTER. XI. |
|
Of the Extent of the Legislative
Power.
|
|
|
|
Sec. 134. THE
great end of men's entering into
society, being the enjoyment of their properties in peace and safety, and the great
instrument and means of that being the laws established in that society; the first and
fundamental positive law of all commonwealths is the establishing of the legislative
power; as the first and fundamental natural law, which is to govern even the legislative
itself, is the preservation of the society, and (as far as will consist with the public
good) of every person in it. This legislative is not only the supreme power of the
common-wealth, but sacred and unalterable in the hands where the community have once
placed it; nor can any edict of any body else, in what form soever conceived, or by what
power soever backed, have the force and obligation of a law, which has not its sanction
from that legislative which the public has chosen and appointed: for without this the law
could not have that, which is absolutely necessary to its being a law,* the consent of the
society, over whom no body can have a power to make laws, but by their own consent, and by
authority received from them; and therefore all the obedience, which by the most solemn
ties any one can be obliged to pay, ultimately terminates in this supreme power, and is
directed by those laws which it enacts: nor can any oaths to any foreign power whatsoever,
or any domestic subordinate power, discharge any member of the society from his obedience
to the legislative, acting pursuant to their trust; nor oblige him to any obedience
contrary to the laws so enacted, or farther than they do allow; it being ridiculous to
imagine one can be tied ultimately to obey any power in the society, which is not the
supreme.
|
|
(* The lawful power of making laws to command whole politic
societies of men, belonging so properly unto the same intire societies, that for any
prince or potentate of what kind soever upon earth, to exercise the same of himself, and
not by express commission immediately and personally received from God, or else by
authority derived at the first from their consent, upon whose persons they impose laws, it
is no better than mere tyranny. Laws they are not therefore which public approbation hath
not made so. Hooker's Eccl. Pol. l. i. sect. 10. Of this point therefore we are to note,
that sith men naturally have no full and perfect power to command whole politic multitudes
of men, therefore utterly without our consent, we could in such sort be at no man's
commandment living. And to be commanded we do consent, when that society, whereof we be a
part, hath at any time before consented, without revoking the same after by the like
universal agreement.
|
|
Laws therefore human, of what kind so ever, are available by
consent. Ibid.)
|
|
Sec. 135. Though the legislative, whether placed in one or
more, whether it be always in being, or only by intervals, though it be the supreme power
in every common-wealth; yet,
|
|
First, It is not, nor can possibly be absolutely arbitrary
over the lives and fortunes of the people: for it being but the joint power of every
member of the society given up to that person, or assembly, which is legislator; it can be
no more than those persons had in a state of nature before they entered into society, and
gave up to the community: for no body can transfer to another more power than he has in
himself; and no body has an absolute arbitrary power over himself, or over any other, to
destroy his own life, or take away the life or property of another. A man, as has been
proved, cannot subject himself to the arbitrary power of another; and having in the state
of nature no arbitrary power over the life, liberty, or possession of another, but only so
much as the law of nature gave him for the preservation of himself, and the rest of
mankind; this is all he doth, or can give up to the common-wealth, and by it to the
legislative power, so that the legislative can have no more than this. Their power, in the
utmost bounds of it, is limited to the public good of the society. It is a power, that
hath no other end but preservation, and therefore can never* have a right to destroy,
enslave, or designedly to impoverish the subjects. The obligations of the law of nature
cease not in society, but only in many cases are drawn closer, and have by human laws
known penalties annexed to them, to inforce their observation. Thus the law of nature
stands as an eternal rule to all men, legislators as well as others. The rules that they
make for other men's actions, must, as well as their own and other men's actions, be
conformable to the law of nature, i.e. to the will of God, of which that is a declaration,
and the fundamental law of nature being the preservation of mankind, no human sanction can
be good, or valid against it.
|
|
(* Two foundations there are which bear up public societies;
the one a natural inclination, whereby all men desire sociable life and fellowship; the
other an order, expresly or secretly agreed upon, touching the manner of their union in
living together: the latter is that which we call the law of a commonweal, the very soul
of a politic body, the parts whereof are by law animated, held together, and set on work
in such actions as the common good requireth. Laws politic, ordained for external order
and regiment amongst men, are never framed as they should be, unless presuming the will of
man to be inwardly obstinate, rebellious, and averse from all obedience to the sacred laws
of his nature; in a word, unless presuming man to be, in regard of his depraved mind,
little better than a wild beast, they do accordingly provide, notwithstanding, so to frame
his outward actions, that they be no hindrance unto the common good, for which societies
are instituted. Unless they do this, they are not perfect. Hooker's Eccl. Pol. l. i. sect.
10.)
|
|
Sec. 136. Secondly,* The legislative, or supreme authority,
cannot assume to its self a power to rule by extemporary arbitrary decrees, but is bound
to dispense justice, and decide the rights of the subject by promulgated standing laws,
and known authorized judges: for the law of nature being unwritten, and so no where to be
found but in the minds of men, they who through passion or interest shall miscite, or
misapply it, cannot so easily be convinced of their mistake where there is no established
judge: and so it serves not, as it ought, to determine the rights, and fence the
properties of those that live under it, especially where every one is judge, interpreter,
and executioner of it too, and that in his own case: and he that has right on his side,
having ordinarily but his own single strength, hath not force enough to defend himself
from injuries, or to punish delinquents. To avoid these inconveniences, which disorder
men's propperties in the state of nature, men unite into societies, that they may have the
united strength of the whole society to secure and defend their properties, and may have
standing rules to bound it, by which every one may know what is his. To this end it is
that men give up all their natural power to the society which they enter into, and the
community put the legislative power into such hands as they think fit, with this trust,
that they shall be governed by declared laws, or else their peace, quiet, and property
will still be at the same uncertainty, as it was in the state of nature.
|
|
(* Human laws are measures in respect of men whose actions
they must direct, howbeit such measures they are as have also their higher rules to be
measured by, which rules are two, the law of God, and the law of nature; so that laws
human must be made according to the general laws of nature, and without contradiction to
any positive law of scripture, otherwise they are ill made. Hooker's Eccl. Pol. l. iii.
sect. 9.
|
|
To constrain men to any thing inconvenient doth seem
unreasonable. Ibid. l. i. sect. 10.)
|
|
Sec. 137. Absolute arbitrary power, or governing without
settled standing laws, can neither of them consist with the ends of society and
government, which men would not quit the freedom of the state of nature for, and tie
themselves up under, were it not to preserve their lives, liberties and fortunes, and by
stated rules of right and property to secure their peace and quiet. It cannot be supposed
that they should intend, had they a power so to do, to give to any one, or more, an
absolute arbitrary power over their persons and estates, and put a force into the
magistrate's hand to execute his unlimited will arbitrarily upon them. This were to put
themselves into a worse condition than the state of nature, wherein they had a liberty to
defend their right against the injuries of others, and were upon equal terms of force to
maintain it, whether invaded by a single man, or many in combination. Whereas by supposing
they have given up themselves to the absolute arbitrary power and will of a legislator,
they have disarmed themselves, and armed him, to make a prey of them when he pleases; he
being in a much worse condition, who is exposed to the arbitrary power of one man, who has
the command of 100,000, than he that is exposed to the arbitrary power of 100,000 single
men; no body being secure, that his will, who has such a command, is better than that of
other men, though his force be 100,000 times stronger. And therefore, whatever form the
common-wealth is under, the ruling power ought to govern by declared and received laws,
and not by extemporary dictates and undetermined resolutions: for then mankind will be in
a far worse condition than in the state of nature, if they shall have armed one, or a few
men with the joint power of a multitude, to force them to obey at pleasure the exorbitant
and unlimited decrees of their sudden thoughts, or unrestrained, and till that moment
unknown wills, without having any measures set down which may guide and justify their
actions: for all the power the government has, being only for the good of the society, as
it ought not to be arbitrary and at pleasure, so it ought to be exercised by established
and promulgated laws; that both the people may know their duty, and be safe and secure
within the limits of the law; and the rulers too kept within their bounds, and not be
tempted, by the power they have in their hands, to employ it to such purposes, and by such
measures, as they would not have known, and own not willingly.
|
|
Sec. 138. Thirdly, The supreme power cannot take from any
man any part of his property without his own consent: for the preservation of property
being the end of government, and that for which men enter into society, it necessarily
supposes and requires, that the people should have property, without which they must be
supposed to lose that, by entering into society, which was the end for which they entered
into it; too gross an absurdity for any man to own. Men therefore in society having
property, they have such a right to the goods, which by the law of the community are
their's, that no body hath a right to take their substance or any part of it from them,
without their own consent: without this they have no property at all; for I have truly no
property in that, which another can by right take from me, when he pleases, against my
consent. Hence it is a mistake to think, that the supreme or legislative power of any
commonwealth, can do what it will, and dispose of the estates of the subject arbitrarily,
or take any part of them at pleasure. This is not much to be feared in governments where
the legislative consists, wholly or in part, in assemblies which are variable, whose
members, upon the dissolution of the assembly, are subjects under the common laws of their
country, equally with the rest. But in governments, where the legislative is in one
lasting assembly always in being, or in one man, as in absolute monarchies, there is
danger still, that they will think themselves to have a distinct interest from the rest of
the community; and so will be apt to increase their own riches and power, by taking what
they think fit from the people: for a man's property is not at all secure, tho' there be
good and equitable laws to set the bounds of it between him and his fellow subjects, if he
who commands those subjects have power to take from any private man, what part he pleases
of his property, and use and dispose of it as he thinks good.
|
|
Sec. 139. But government, into whatsoever hands it is put,
being, as I have before shewed, intrusted with this condition, and for this end, that men
might have and secure their properties; the prince, or senate, however it may have power
to make laws, for the regulating of property between the subjects one amongst another, yet
can never have a power to take to themselves the whole, or any part of the subjects
property, without their own consent: for this would be in effect to leave them no property
at all. And to let us see, that even absolute power, where it is necessary, is not
arbitrary by being absolute, but is still limited by that reason, and confined to those
ends, which required it in some cases to be absolute, we need look no farther than the
common practice of martial discipline: for the preservation of the army, and in it of the
whole common-wealth, requires an absolute obedience to the command of every superior
officer, and it is justly death to disobey or dispute the most dangerous or unreasonable
of them; but yet we see, that neither the serjeant, that could command a soldier to march
up to the mouth of a cannon, or stand in a breach, where he is almost sure to perish, can
command that soldier to give him one penny of his money; nor the general, that can condemn
him to death for deserting his post, or for not obeying the most desperate orders, can
yet, with all his absolute power of life and death, dispose of one farthing of that
soldier's estate, or seize one jot of his goods; whom yet he can command any thing, and
hang for the least disobedience; because such a blind obedience is necessary to that end,
for which the commander has his power, viz. the preservation of the rest; but the
disposing of his goods has nothing to do with it.
|
|
Sec. 140. It is true, governments cannot be supported
without great charge, and it is fit every one who enjoys his share of the protection,
should pay out of his estate his proportion for the maintenance of it. But still it must
be with his own consent, i.e. the consent of the majority, giving it either by themselves,
or their representatives chosen by them: for if any one shall claim a power to lay and
levy taxes on the people, by his own authority, and without such consent of the people, he
thereby invades the fundamental law of property, and subverts the end of government: for
what property have I in that, which another may by right take, when he pleases, to
himself?
|
|
Sec. 141. Fourthly, The legislative cannot transfer the
power of making laws to any other hands: for it being but a delegated power from the
people, they who have it cannot pass it over to others. The people alone can appoint the
form of the common-wealth, which is by constituting the legislative, and appointing in
whose hands that shall be. And when the people have said, We will submit to rules, and be
governed by laws made by such men, and in such forms, no body else can say other men shall
make laws for them; nor can the people be bound by any laws, but such as are enacted by
those whom they have chosen, and authorized to make laws for them. The power of the
legislative, being derived from the people by a positive voluntary grant and institution,
can be no other than what that positive grant conveyed, which being only to make laws, and
not to make legislators, the legislative can have no power to transfer their authority of
making laws, and place it in other hands.
|
|
Sec. 142. These are the bounds which the trust, that is put
in them by the society, and the law of God and nature, have set to the legislative power
of every common-wealth, in all forms of government.
|
|
First, They are to govern by promulgated established laws,
not to be varied in particular cases, but to have one rule for rich and poor, for the
favourite at court, and the country man at plough.
|
|
Secondly, These laws also ought to be designed for no other
end ultimately, but the good of the people.
|
|
Thirdly, They must not raise taxes on the property of the
people, without the consent of the people, given by themselves, or their deputies. And
this properly concerns only such governments where the legislative is always in being, or
at least where the people have not reserved any part of the legislative to deputies, to be
from time to time chosen by themselves.
|
|
Fourthly, The legislative neither must nor can transfer the
power of making laws to any body else, or place it any where, but where the people have.
|
|
|
|
|