CHAPTER. XIX. |
|
Of the Dissolution of Government. |
|
|
|
Sec. 211. HE
that will with any clearness speak
of the dissolution of government, ought in the first place to distinguish between the
dissolution of the society and the dissolution of the government. That which makes the
community, and brings men out of the loose state of nature, into one politic society, is
the agreement which every one has with the rest to incorporate, and act as one body, and
so be one distinct commonwealth. The usual, and almost only way whereby this union is
dissolved, is the inroad of foreign force mak ing a conquest upon them: for in that case,
(not being able to maintain and support themselves, as one intire and independent body)
the union belonging to that body which consisted therein, must necessarily cease, and so
every one return to the state he was in before, with a liberty to shift for himself, and
provide for his own safety, as he thinks fit, in some other society. Whenever the society
is dissolved, it is certain the government of that society cannot remain. Thus conquerors
swords often cut up governments by the roots, and mangle societies to pieces, separating
the subdued or scattered multitude from the protection of, and dependence on, that society
which ought to have preserved them from violence. The world is too well instructed in, and
too forward to allow of, this way of dissolving of governments, to need any more to be
said of it; and there wants not much argument to prove, that where the society is
dissolved, the government cannot remain; that being as impossible, as for the frame of an
house to subsist when the materials of it are scattered and dissipated by a whirl-wind, or
jumbled into a confused heap by an earthquake.
|
|
Sec. 212. Besides this over-turning from without,
governments are dissolved from within,
|
|
First, When the legislative is altered. Civil society being
a state of peace, amongst those who are of it, from whom the state of war is excluded by
the umpirage, which they have provided in their legislative, for the ending all
differences that may arise amongst any of them, it is in their legislative, that the
members of a commonwealth are united, and combined together into one coherent living body.
This is the soul that gives form, life, and unity, to the common-wealth: from hence the
several members have their mutual influence, sympathy, and connexion: and therefore, when
the legislative is broken, or dissolved, dissolution and death follows: for the essence
and union of the society consisting in having one will, the legislative, when once
established by the majority, has the declaring, and as it were keeping of that will. The
constitution of the legislative is the first and fundamental act of society, whereby
provision is made for the continuation of their union, under the direction of persons, and
bonds of laws, made by persons authorized thereunto, by the consent and appointment of the
people, without which no one man, or number of men, amongst them, can have authority of
making laws that shall be binding to the rest. When any one, or more, shall take upon them
to make laws, whom the people have not appointed so to do, they make laws without
authority, which the people are not therefore bound to obey; by which means they come
again to be out of subjection, and may constitute to themselves a new legislative, as they
think best, being in full liberty to resist the force of those, who without authority
would impose any thing upon them. Every one is at the disposure of his own will, when
those who had, by the delegation of the society, the declaring of the public will, are
excluded from it, and others usurp the place, who have no such authority or delegation.
|
|
Sec. 213. This being usually brought about by such in the
commonwealth who misuse the power they have; it is hard to consider it aright, and know at
whose door to lay it, without knowing the form of government in which it happens. Let us
suppose then the legislative placed in the concurrence of three distinct persons.
|
|
1. A single hereditary person, having the constant, supreme,
executive power, and with it the power of convoking and dissolving the other two within
certain periods of time.
|
|
2. An assembly of hereditary nobility. |
|
3. An assembly of representatives chosen, pro tempore, by
the people. Such a form of government supposed, it is evident,
|
|
Sec. 214. First, That when such a single person, or prince,
sets up his own arbitrary will in place of the laws, which are the will of the society,
declared by the legislative, then the legislative is changed: for that being in effect the
legislative, whose rules and laws are put in execution, and required to be obeyed; when
other laws are set up, and other rules pretended, and inforced, than what the legislative,
constituted by the society, have enacted, it is plain that the legislative is changed.
Whoever introduces new laws, not being thereunto authorized by the fundamental appointment
of the society, or subverts the old, disowns and overturns the power by which they were
made, and so sets up a new legislative.
|
|
Sec. 215. Secondly, When the prince hinders the legislative
from assembling in its due time, or from acting freely, pursuant to those ends for which
it was constituted, the legislative is altered: for it is not a certain number of men, no,
nor their meeting, unless they have also freedom of debating, and leisure of perfecting,
what is for the good of the society, wherein the legislative consists: when these are
taken away or altered, so as to deprive the society of the due exercise of their power,
the legislative is truly altered; for it is not names that constitute governments, but the
use and exercise of those powers that were intended to accompany them; so that he, who
takes away the freedom, or hinders the acting of the legislative in its due seasons, in
effect takes away the legislative, and puts an end to the government.
|
|
Sec. 216. Thirdly, When, by the arbitrary power of the
prince, the electors, or ways of election, are altered, without the consent, and contrary
to the common interest of the people, there also the legislative is altered: for, if
others than those whom the society hath authorized thereunto, do chuse, or in another way
than what the society hath prescribed, those chosen are not the legislative appointed by
the people.
|
|
Sec. 217. Fourthly, The delivery also of the people into the
subjection of a foreign power, either by the prince, or by the legislative, is certainly a
change of the legislative, and so a dissolution of the government: for the end why people
entered into society being to be preserved one intire, free, independent society, to be
governed by its own laws; this is lost, whenever they are given up into the power of
another.
|
|
Sec. 218. Why, in such a constitution as this, the
dissolution of the government in these cases is to be imputed to the prince, is evident;
because he, having the force, treasure and offices of the state to employ, and often
persuading himself, or being flattered by others, that as supreme magistrate he is
uncapable of controul; he alone is in a condition to make great advances toward such
changes, under pretence of lawful authority, and has it in his hands to terrify or
suppress opposers, as factious, seditious, and enemies to the government: whereas no other
part of the legislative, or people, is capable by themselves to attempt any alteration of
the legislative, without open and visible rebellion, apt enough to be taken notice of,
which, when it prevails, produces effects very little different from foreign conquest.
Besides, the prince in such a form of government, having the power of dissolving the other
parts of the legislative, and thereby rendering them private persons, they can never in
opposition to him, or without his concurrence, alter the legislative by a law, his conse
power, neglects and abandons that charge, so that the laws already made can no longer be
put in execution. This is demonstratively to reduce all to anarchy, and so effectually to
dissolve the government: for laws not being made for themselves, but to be, by their
execution, the bonds of the society, to keep every part of the body politic in its due
place and function; when that totally ceases, the government visibly ceases, and the
people become a confused multitude, without order or connexion. Where there is no longer
the administration of justice, for the securing of men's rights, nor any remaining power
within the community to direct the force, or provide for the necessities of the public,
there certainly is no government left. Where the laws cannot be executed, it is all one as
if there were no laws; and a government without laws is, I suppose, a mystery in politics,
unconceivable to human capacity, and inconsistent with human society.
|
|
Sec. 219. There is one way more whereby such a government
may be dissolved, and that is: When he who has the supreme executive power neglects and
abandons that charge, so that the laws already made can no longer be put in execution;
this is demonstratively to reduce all to anarchy, and so effectively to dissolve the
government. For laws not being made for themselves, but to be, by their execution, the
bonds of the society to keep every part of the body politic in its due place and function.
When that totally ceases, the government visibly ceases, and the people become a confused
multitude without order or connection. Where there is no longer the administration of
justice for the securing of menā²s rights, nor any remaining power within the
community to direct the force, or provide for the necessities of the public, there
certainly is no government left. Where the laws cannot be executed it is all one as if
there were no laws, and a government without laws is, I suppose, a mystery in politics
inconceivable to human capacity, and inconsistent with human society.
|
|
Sec. 220. In these and the like cases, when the government
is dissolved, the people are at liberty to provide for themselves, by erecting a new
legislative, differing from the other, by the change of persons, or form, or both, as they
shall find it most for their safety and good: for the society can never, by the fault of
another, lose the native and original right it has to preserve itself, which can only be
done by a settled legislative, and a fair and impartial execution of the laws made by it.
But the state of mankind is not so miserable that they are not capable of using this
remedy, till it be too late to look for any. To tell people they may provide for
themselves, by erecting a new legislative, when by oppression, artifice, or being
delivered over to a foreign power, their old one is gone, is only to tell them, they may
expect relief when it is too late, and the evil is past cure. This is in effect no more
than to bid them first be slaves, and then to take care of their liberty; and when their
chains are on, tell them, they may act like freemen. This, if barely so, is rather mockery
than relief; and men can never be secure from tyranny, if there be no means to escape it
till they are perfectly under it: and therefore it is, that they have not only a right to
get out of it, but to prevent it.
|
|
Sec. 221. There is therefore, secondly, another way whereby
governments are dissolved, and that is, when the legislative, or the prince, either of
them, act contrary to their trust. First, The legislative acts against the trust reposed
in them, when they endeavour to invade the property of the subject, and to make
themselves, or any part of the community, masters, or arbitrary disposers of the lives,
liberties, or fortunes of the people.
|
|
Sec. 222. The reason why men enter into society, is the
preservation of their property; and the end why they chuse and authorize a legislative,
is, that there may be laws made, and rules set, as guards and fences to the properties of
all the members of the society, to limit the power, and moderate the dominion, of every
part and member of the society: for since it can never be supposed to be the will of the
society, that the legislative should have a power to destroy that which every one designs
to secure, by entering into society, and for which the people submitted themselves to
legislators of their own making; whenever the legislators endeavour to take away, and
destroy the property of the people, or to reduce them to slavery under arbitrary power,
they put themselves into a state of war with the people, who are thereupon absolved from
any farther obedience, and are left to the common refuge, which God hath provided for all
men, against force and violence. Whensoever therefore the legislative shall transgress
this fundamental rule of society; and either by ambition, fear, folly or corruption,
endeavour to grasp themselves, or put into the hands of any other, an absolute power over
the lives, liberties, and estates of the people; by this breach of trust they forfeit the
power the people had put into their hands for quite contrary ends, and it devolves to the
people, who. have a right to resume their original liberty, and, by the establishment of a
new legislative, (such as they shall think fit) provide for their own safety and security,
which is the end for which they are in society. What I have said here, concerning the
legislative in general, holds true also concerning the supreme executor, who having a
double trust put in him, both to have a part in the legislative, and the supreme execution
of the law, acts against both, when he goes about to set up his own arbitrary will as the
law of the society. He acts also contrary to his trust, when he either employs the force,
treasure, and offices of the society, to corrupt the representatives, and gain them to his
purposes; or openly preengages the electors, and prescribes to their choice, such, whom he
has, by sollicitations, threats, promises, or otherwise, won to his designs; and employs
them to bring in such, who have promised before-hand what to vote, and what to enact. Thus
to regulate candidates and electors, and new-model the ways of election, what is it but to
cut up the government by the roots, and poison the very fountain of public security? for
the people having reserved to themselves the choice of their representatives, as the fence
to their properties, could do it for no other end, but that they might always be freely
chosen, and so chosen, freely act, and advise, as the necessity of the common-wealth, and
the public good should, upon examination, and mature debate, be judged to require. This,
those who give their votes before they hear the debate, and have weighed the reasons on
all sides, are not capable of doing. To prepare such an assembly as this, and endeavour to
set up the declared abettors of his own will, for the true representatives of the people,
and the law-makers of the society, is certainly as great a breach of trust, and as perfect
a declaration of a design to subvert the government, as is possible to be met with. To
which, if one shall add rewards and punishments visibly employed to the same end, and all
the arts of perverted law made use of, to take off and destroy all that stand in the way
of such a design, and will not comply and consent to betray the liberties of their
country, it will be past doubt what is doing. What power they ought to have in the
society, who thus employ it contrary to the trust went along with it in its first
institution, is easy to determine; and one cannot but see, that he, who has once attempted
any such thing as this, cannot any longer be trusted.
|
|
Sec. 223. To this perhaps it will be said, that the people
being ignorant, and always discontented, to lay the foundation of government in the
unsteady opinion and uncertain humour of the people, is to expose it to certain ruin; and
no government will be able long to subsist, if the people may set up a new legislative,
whenever they take offence at the old one. To this I answer, Quite the contrary. People
are not so easily got out of their old forms, as some are apt to suggest. They are hardly
to be prevailed with to amend the acknowledged faults in the frame they have been
accustomed to. And if there be any original defects, or adventitious ones introduced by
time, or corruption; it is not an easy thing to get them changed, even when all the world
sees there is an opportunity for it. This slowness and aversion in the people to quit
their old constitutions, has, in the many revolutions which have been seen in this
kingdom, in this and former ages, still kept us to, or, after some interval of fruitless
attempts, still brought us back again to our old legislative of king, lords and commons:
and whatever provocations have made the crown be taken from some of our princes heads,
they never carried the people so far as to place it in another line.
|
|
Sec. 224. But it will be said, this hypothesis lays a
ferment for frequent rebellion. To which I answer,
|
|
First, No more than any other hypothesis: for when the
people are made miserable, and find themselves exposed to the ill usage of arbitrary
power, cry up their governors, as much as you will, for sons of Jupiter; let them be
sacred and divine, descended, or authorized from heaven; give them out for whom or what
you please, the same will happen. The people generally ill treated, and contrary to right,
will be ready upon any occasion to ease themselves of a burden that sits heavy upon them.
They will wish, and seek for the opportunity, which in the change, weakness and accidents
of human affairs, seldom delays long to offer itself. He must have lived but a little
while in the world, who has not seen examples of this in his time; and he must have read
very little, who cannot produce examples of it in all sorts of governments in the world.
|
|
Sec. 225. Secondly, I answer, such revolutions happen not
upon every little mismanagement in public affairs. Great mistakes in the ruling part, many
wrong and inconvenient laws, and all the slips of human frailty, will be born by the
people without mutiny or murmur. But if a long train of abuses, prevarications and
artifices, all tending the same way, make the design visible to the people, and they
cannot but feel what they lie under, and see whither they are going; it is not to be
wondered, that they should then rouze themselves, and endeavour to put the rule into such
hands which may secure to them the ends for which government was at first erected; and
without which, ancient names, and specious forms, are so far from being better, that they
are much worse, than the state of nature, or pure anarchy; the inconveniencies being all
as great and as near, but the remedy farther off and more difficult.
|
|
Sec. 226. Thirdly, I answer, that this doctrine of a power
in the people of providing for their safety a-new, by a new legislative, when their
legislators have acted contrary to their trust, by invading their property, is the best
fence against rebellion, and the probablest means to hinder it: for rebellion being an
opposition, not to persons, but authority, which is founded only in the constitutions and
laws of the government; those, whoever they be, who by force break through, and by force
justify their violation of them, are truly and properly rebels: for when men, by entering
into society and civil-government, have excluded force, and introduced laws for the
preservation of property, peace, and unity amongst themselves, those who set up force
again in opposition to the laws, do rebellare, that is, bring back again the state of war,
and are properly rebels: which they who are in power, (by the pretence they have to
authority, the temptation of force they have in their hands, and the flattery of those
about them) being likeliest to do; the properest way to prevent the evil, is to shew them
the danger and injustice of it, who are under the greatest temptation to run into it.
|
|
Sec. 227. In both the fore-mentioned cases, when either the
legislative is changed, or the legislators act contrary to the end for which they were
constituted; those who are guilty are guilty of rebellion: for if any one by force takes
away the established legislative of any society, and the laws by them made, pursuant to
their trust, he thereby takes away the umpirage, which every one had consented to, for a
peaceable decision of all their controversies, and a bar to the state of war amongst them.
They, who remove, or change the legislative, take away this decisive power, which no body
can have, but by the appointment and consent of the people; and so destroying the
authority which the people did, and no body else can set up, and introducing a power which
the people hath not authorized, they actually introduce a state of war, which is that of
force without authority: and thus, by removing the legislative established by the society,
(in whose decisions the people acquiesced and united, as to that of their own will) they
untie the knot, and expose the people a-new to the state of war, And if those, who by
force take away the legislative, are rebels, the legislators themselves, as has been
shewn, can be no less esteemed so; when they, who were set up for the protection, and
preservation of the people, their liberties and properties, shall by force invade and
endeavour to take them away; and so they putting themselves into a state of war with those
who made them the protectors and guardians of their peace, are properly, and with the
greatest aggravation, rebellantes, rebels.
|
|
Sec. 228. But if they, who say it lays a foundation for
rebellion, mean that it may occasion civil wars, or intestine broils, to tell the people
they are absolved from obedience when illegal attempts are made upon their liberties or
properties, and may oppose the unlawful violence of those who were their magistrates, when
they invade their properties contrary to the trust put in them; and that therefore this
doctrine is not to be allowed, being so destructive to the peace of the world: they may as
well say, upon the same ground, that honest men may not oppose robbers or pirates, because
this may occasion disorder or bloodshed. If any mischief come in such cases, it is not to
be charged upon him who defends his own right, but on him that invades his neighbours. If
the innocent honest man must quietly quit all he has, for peace sake, to him who will lay
violent hands upon it, I desire it may be considered, what a kind of peace there will be
in the world, which consists only in violence and rapine; and which is to be maintained
only for the benefit of robbers and oppressors. VVho would not think it an admirable peace
betwix the mighty and the mean, when the lamb, without resistance, yielded his throat to
be torn by the imperious wolf? Polyphemus's den gives us a perfect pattern of such a
peace, and such a government, wherein Ulysses and his companions had nothing to do, but
quietly to suffer themselves to be devoured. And no doubt Ulysses, who was a prudent man,
preached up passive obedience, and exhorted them to a quiet submission, by representing to
them of what concernment peace was to mankind; and by shewing the inconveniences might
happen, if they should offer to resist Polyphemus, who had now the power over them.
|
|
Sec. 229. The end of government is the good of mankind; and
which is best for mankind, that the people should be always exposed to the boundless will
of tyranny, or that the rulers should be sometimes liable to be opposed, when they grow
exorbitant in the use of their power, and employ it for the destruction, and not the
preservation of the properties of their people?
|
|
Sec. 230. Nor let any one say, that mischief can arise from
hence, as often as it shall please a busy head, or turbulent spirit, to desire the
alteration of the government. It is true, such men may stir, whenever they please; but it
will be only to their own just ruin and perdition: for till the mischief be grown general,
and the ill designs of the rulers become visible, or their attempts sensible to the
greater part, the people, who are more disposed to suffer than right themselves by
resistance, are not apt to stir. The examples of particular injustice, or oppression of
here and there an unfortunate man, moves them not. But if they universally have a
persuation, grounded upon manifest evidence, that designs are carrying on against their
liberties, and the general course and tendency of things cannot but give them strong
suspicions of the evil intention of their governors, who is to be blamed for it? Who can
help it, if they, who might avoid it, bring themselves into this suspicion? Are the people
to be blamed, if they have the sense of rational creatures, and can think of things no
otherwise than as they find and feel them? And is it not rather their fault, who put
things into such a posture, that they would not have them thought to be as they are? I
grant, that the pride, ambition, and turbulency of private men have sometimes caused great
disorders in commonwealths, and factions have been fatal to states and kingdoms. But
whether the mischief hath oftener begun in the peoples wantonness, and a desire to cast
off the lawful authority of their rulers, or in the rulers insolence, and endeavours to
get and exercise an arbitrary power over their people; whether oppression, or
disobedience, gave the first rise to the disorder, I leave it to impartial history to
determine. This I am sure, whoever, either ruler or subject, by force goes about to invade
the rights of either prince or people, and lays the foundation for overturning the
constitution and frame of any just government, is highly guilty of the greatest crime, I
think, a man is capable of, being to answer for all those mischiefs of blood, rapine, and
desolation, which the breaking to pieces of governments bring on a country. And he who
does it, is justly to be esteemed the common enemy and pest of mankind, and is to be
treated accordingly.
|
|
Sec. 231. That subjects or foreigners, attempting by force
on the properties of any people, may be resisted with force, is agreed on all hands. But
that magistrates, doing the same thing, may be resisted, hath of late been denied: as if
those who had the greatest privileges and advantages by the law, had thereby a power to
break those laws, by which alone they were set in a better place than their brethren:
whereas their offence is thereby the greater, both as being ungrateful for the greater
share they have by the law, and breaking also that trust, which is put into their hands by
their brethren.
|
|
Sec. 232. Whosoever uses force without right, as every one
does in society, who does it without law, puts himself into a state of war with those
against whom he so uses it; and in that state all former ties are cancelled, all other
rights cease, and every one has a right to defend himself, and to resist the aggressor.
This is so evident, that Barclay himself, that great assertor of the power and sacredness
of kings, is forced to confess, That it is lawful for the people, in some cases, to resist
their king; and that too in a chapter, wherein he pretends to shew, that the divine law
shuts up the people from all manner of rebellion. Whereby it is evident, even by his own
doctrine, that, since they may in some cases resist, all resisting of princes is not
rebellion. His words are these.
|
|
Quod siquis dicat, Ergone populus tyrannicae crudelitati
& furori jugulum semper praebebit? Ergone multitude civitates suas fame, ferro, &
flamma vastari, seque, conjuges, & liberos fortunae ludibrio & tyranni libidini
exponi, inque omnia vitae pericula omnesque miserias & molestias a rege deduci
patientur? Num illis quod omni animantium generi est a natura tributum, denegari debet, ut
sc. vim vi repellant, seseq; ab injuria, tueantur? Huic breviter responsum sit, Populo
universo negari defensionem, quae juris naturalis est, neque ultionem quae praeter naturam
est adversus regem concedi debere. Quapropter si rex non in singulares tantum personas
aliquot privatum odium exerceat, sed corpus etiam reipublicae, cujus ipse caput est, i.e.
totum populum, vel insignem aliquam ejus partem immani & intoleranda saevitia seu
tyrannide divexet; populo, quidem hoc casu resistendi ac tuendi se ab injuria potestas
competit, sed tuendi se tantum, non enim in principem invadendi: & restituendae
injuriae illatae, non recedendi a debita reverentia propter acceptam injuriam. Praesentem
denique impetum propulsandi non vim praeteritam ulciscenti jus habet. Horum enim alterum a
natura est, ut vitam scilicet corpusque tueamur. Alterum vero contra naturam, ut inferior
de superiori supplicium sumat. Quod itaque populus malum, antequam factum sit, impedire
potest, ne fiat, id postquam factum est, in regem authorem sceleris vindicare non potest:
populus igitur hoc amplius quam privatus quispiam habet: quod huic, vel ipsis adversariis
judicibus, excepto Buchanano, nullum nisi in patientia remedium superest. Cum ille si
intolerabilis tyrannus est (modicum enim ferre omnino debet) resistere cum reverentia
possit, Barclay contra Monarchom. 1. iii. c. 8.
|
|
In English thus: |
|
Sec. 233. But if any one should ask, Must the people then
always lay themselves open to the cruelty and rage of tyranny? Must they see their cities
pillaged, and laid in ashes, their wives and children exposed to the tyrant's lust and
fury, and themselves and families reduced by their king to ruin, and all the miseries of
want and oppression, and yet sit still? Must men alone be debarred the common privilege of
opposing force with force, which nature allows so freely to all other creatures for their
preservation from injury? I answer: Self-defence is a part of the law of nature; nor can
it be denied the community, even against the king himself: but to revenge themselves upon
him, must by no means be allowed them; it being not agreeable to that law. Wherefore if
the king shall shew an hatred, not only to some particular persons, but sets himself
against the body of the common-wealth, whereof he is the head, and shall, with intolerable
ill usage, cruelly tyrannize over the whole, or a considerable part of the people, in this
case the people have a right to resist and defend themselves from injury: but it must be
with this caution, that they only defend themselves, but do not attack their prince: they
may repair the damages received, but must not for any provocation exceed the bounds of due
reverence and respect. They may repulse the present attempt, but must not revenge past
violences: for it is natural for us to defend life and limb, but that an inferior should
punish a superior, is against nature. The mischief which is designed them, the people may
prevent before it be done; but when it is done, they must not revenge it on the king,
though author of the villany. This therefore is the privilege of the people in general,
above what any private person hath; that particular men are allowed by our adversaries
themselves (Buchanan only excepted) to have no other remedy but patience; but the body of
the people may with respect resist intolerable tyranny; for when it is but moderate, they
ought to endure it.
|
|
Sec. 234. Thus far that great advocate of monarchical power
allows of resistance.
|
|
Sec. 235. It is true, he has annexed two limitations to it,
to no purpose:
|
|
First, He says, it must be with reverence. |
|
Secondly, It must be without retribution, or punishment; and
the reason he gives is, because an inferior cannot punish a superior.
|
|
First, How to resist force without striking again, or how to
strike with reverence, will need some skill to make intelligible. He that shall oppose an
assault only with a shield to receive the blows, or in any more respectful posture,
without a sword in his hand, to abate the confidence and force of the assailant, will
quickly be at an end of his resistance, and will find such a defence serve only to draw on
himself the worse usage. This is as ridiculous a way of resisting, as juvenal thought it
of fighting; ubi tu pulsas, ego vapulo tantum. And the success of the combat will be
unavoidably the same he there describes it:
|
|
Libertas pauperis haec est:
Pulsatus rogat, & pugnis concisus, adorat,
Ut liceat paucis cum dentibus inde reverti.
|
|
This will always be the event of such an imaginary
resistance, where men may not strike again. He therefore who may resist, must be allowed
to strike. And then let our author, or any body else, join a knock on the head, or a cut
on the face, with as much reverence and respect as he thinks fit. He that can reconcile
blows and reverence, may, for aught I know, desire for his pains, a civil, respectful
cudgeling where-ever he can meet with it.
|
|
Secondly, As to his second, An inferior cannot punish a
superior; that is true, generally speaking, whilst he is his superior. But to resist force
with force, being the state of war that levels the parties, cancels all former relation of
reverence, respect, and superiority: and then the odds that remains, is, that he, who
opposes the unjust agressor, has this superiority over him, that he has a right, when he
prevails, to punish the offender, both for the breach of the peace, and all the evils that
followed upon it. Barclay therefore, in another place, more coherently to himself, denies
it to be lawful to resist a king in any case. But he there assigns two cases, whereby a
king may un-king himself. His words are,
|
|
Quid ergo, nulline casus incidere possunt quibus populo sese
erigere atque in regem impotentius dominantem arma capere & invadere jure suo suaque
authoritate liceat? Nulli certe quamdiu rex manet. Semper enim ex divinis id obstat, Regem
honorificato; & qui potestati resistit, Dei ordinationi resisit: non alias igitur in
eum populo potestas est quam si id committat propter quod ipso jure rex esse desinat. Tunc
enim se ipse principatu exuit atque in privatis constituit liber: hoc modo populus &
superior efficitur, reverso ad eum sc. jure illo quod ante regem inauguratum in interregno
habuit. At sunt paucorum generum commissa ejusmodi quae hunc effectum pariunt. At ego cum
plurima animo perlustrem, duo tantum invenio, duos, inquam, casus quibus rex ipso facto ex
rege non regem se facit & omni honore & dignitate regali atque in subditos
potestate destituit; quorum etiam meminit Winzerus. Horum unus est, Si regnum disperdat,
quemadmodum de Nerone fertur, quod is nempe senatum populumque Romanum, atque adeo urbem
ipsam ferro flammaque vastare, ac novas sibi sedes quaerere decrevisset. Et de Caligula,
quod palam denunciarit se neque civem neque principem senatui amplius fore, inque animo
habuerit interempto utriusque ordinis electissimo quoque Alexandriam commigrare, ac ut
populum uno ictu interimeret, unam ei cervicem optavit. Talia cum rex aliquis meditator
& molitur serio, omnem regnandi curam & animum ilico abjicit, ac proinde imperium
in subditos amittit, ut dominus servi pro derelicto habiti dominium.
|
|
Sec. 236. Alter casus est, Si rex in alicujus clientelam se
contulit, ac regnum quod liberum a majoribus & populo traditum accepit, alienae
ditioni mancipavit. Nam tunc quamvis forte non ea mente id agit populo plane ut
incommodet: tamen quia quod praecipuum est regiae dignitatis amifit, ut summus scilicet in
regno secundum Deum sit, & solo Deo inferior, atque populum etiam totum ignorantem vel
invitum, cujus libertatem sartam & tectam conservare debuit, in alterius gentis
ditionem & potestatem dedidit; hac velut quadam regni ab alienatione effecit, ut nec
quod ipse in regno imperium habuit retineat, nec in eum cui collatum voluit, juris
quicquam transferat; atque ita eo facto liberum jam & suae potestatis populum
relinquit, cujus rei exemplum unum annales Scotici suppeditant. Barclay contra Monarchom.
1. iii. c. 16.
|
|
Which in English runs thus: |
|
Sec. 237. What then, can there no case happen wherein the
people may of right, and by their own authority, help themselves, take arms, and set upon
their king, imperiously domineering over them? None at all, whilst he remains a king.
Honour the king, and he that resists the power, resists the ordinance of God; are divine
oracles that will never permit it, The people therefore can never come by a power over
him, unless he does something that makes him cease to be a king: for then he divests
himself of his crown and dignity, and returns to the state of a private man, and the
people become free and superior, the power which they had in the interregnum, before they
crowned him king, devolving to them again. But there are but few miscarriages which bring
the matter to this state. After considering it well on all sides, I can find but two. Two
cases there are, I say, whereby a king, ipso facto, becomes no king, and loses all power
and regal authority over his people; which are also taken notice of by Winzerus.
|
|
The first is, If he endeavour to overturn the government,
that is, if he have a purpose and design to ruin the kingdom and commonwealth, as it is
recorded of Nero, that he resolved to cut off the senate and people of Rome, lay the city
waste with fire and sword, and then remove to some other place. And of Caligula, that he
openly declared, that he would be no longer a head to the people or senate, and that he
had it in his thoughts to cut off the worthiest men of both ranks, and then retire to
Alexandria: and he wisht that the people had but one neck, that he might dispatch them all
at a blow, Such designs as these, when any king harbours in his thoughts, and seriously
promotes, he immediately gives up all care and thought of the common-wealth; and
consequently forfeits the power of governing his subjects, as a master does the dominion
over his slaves whom he hath abandoned.
|
|
Sec. 238. The other case is, When a king makes himself the
dependent of another, and subjects his kingdom which his ancestors left him, and the
people put free into his hands, to the dominion of another: for however perhaps it may not
be his intention to prejudice the people; yet because he has hereby lost the principal
part of regal dignity, viz. to be next and immediately under God, supreme in his kingdom;
and also because he betrayed or forced his people, whose liberty he ought to have
carefully preserved, into the power and dominion of a foreign nation. By this, as. it
were, alienation of his kingdom, he himself loses the power he had in it before, without
transferring any the least right to those on whom he would have bestowed it; and so by
this act sets the people free, and leaves them at their own disposal. One example of this
is to be found in the Scotch Annals.
|
|
Sec. 239. In these cases Barclay, the great champion of
absolute monarchy, is forced to allow, that a king may be resisted, and ceases to be a
king. That is, in short, not to multiply cases, in whatsoever he has no authority, there
he is no king, and may be resisted: for wheresoever the authority ceases, the king ceases
too, and becomes like other men who have no authority. And these two cases he instances
in, differ little from those above mentioned, to be destructive to governments, only that
he has omitted the principle from which his doctrine flows: and that is, the breach of
trust, in not preserving the form of government agreed on, and in not intending the end of
government itself, which is the public good and preservation of property. When a king has
dethroned himself, and put himself in a state of war with his people, what shall hinder
them from prosecuting him who is no king, as they would any other man, who has put himself
into a state of war with them, Barclay, and those of his opinion, would do well to tell
us. This farther I desire may be taken notice of out of Barclay, that he says, The
mischief that is designed them, the people may prevent before it be clone: whereby he
allows resistance when tyranny is but in design. Such designs as these (says he) when any
king harbours in his thoughts and seriously promotes, he immediately gives up all care and
thought of the common-wealth; so that, according to him, the neglect of the public good is
to be taken as an evidence of such design, or at least for a sufficient cause of
resistance. And the reason of all, he gives in these words, Because he betrayed or forced
his people, whose liberty he ought carefully to have preserved. What he adds, into the
power and dominion of a foreign nation, signifies nothing, the fault and forfeiture lying
in the loss of their liberty, which he ought to have preserved, and not in any distinction
of the persons to whose dominion they were subjected. The peoples right is equally
invaded, and their liberty lost, whether they are made slaves to any of their own, or a
foreign nation; and in this lies the injury, and against this only have they the right of
defence. And there are instances to be found in all countries, which shew, that it is not
the change of nations in the persons of their governors, but the change of government,
that gives the offence. Bilson, a bishop of our church, and a great stickler for the power
and prerogative of princes, does, if I mistake not, in his treatise of Christian
subjection, acknowledge, that princes may forfeit their power, and their title to the
obedience of their subjects; and if there needed authority in a case where reason is so
plain, I could send my reader to Bracton, Fortescue, and the author of the Mirrour, and
others, writers that cannot be suspected to be ignorant of our government, or enemies to
it. But I thought Hooker alone might be enough to satisfy those men, who relying on him
for their ecclesiastical polity, are by a strange fate carried to deny those principles
upon which he builds it. Whether they are herein made the tools of cunninger workmen, to
pull down their own fabric, they were best look. This I am sure, their civil policy is so
new, so dangerous, and so destructive to both rulers and people, that as former ages never
could bear the broaching of it; so it may be hoped, those to come, redeemed from the
impositions of these Egyptian under-task-masters, will abhor the memory of such servile
flatterers, who, whilst it seemed to serve their turn, resolved all government into
absolute tyranny, and would have all men born to, what their mean souls fitted them for,
slavery.
|
|
Sec. 240. Here, it is like, the common question will be
made, Who shall be judge, whether the prince or legislative act contrary to their trust?
This, perhaps, ill-affected and factious men may spread amongst the people, when the
prince only makes use of his due prerogative. To this I reply, The people shall be judge;
for who shall be judge whether his trustee or deputy acts well, and according to the trust
reposed in him, but he who deputes him, and must, by having deputed him, have still a
power to discard him, when he fails in his trust? If this be reasonable in particular
cases of private men, why should it be otherwise in that of the greatest moment, where the
welfare of millions is concerned, and also where the evil, if not prevented, is greater,
and the redress very difficult, dear, and dangerous?
|
|
Sec. 241. But farther, this question, (Who shall be judge?)
cannot mean, that there is no judge at all: for where there is no judicature on earth, to
decide controversies amongst men, God in heaven is judge. He alone, it is true, is judge
of the right. But every man is judge for himself, as in all other cases, so in this,
whether another hath put himself into a state of war with him, and whether he should
appeal to the Supreme Judge, as leptha did.
|
|
Sec. 242. If a controversy arise betwixt a prince and some
of the people, in a matter where the law is silent, or doubtful, and the thing be of great
consequence, I should think the proper umpire, in such a case, should be the body of the
people: for in cases where the prince hath a trust reposed in him, and is dispensed from
the common ordinary rules of the law; there, if any men find themselves aggrieved, and
think the prince acts contrary to, or beyond that trust, who so proper to judge as the
body of the people, (who, at first, lodged that trust in him) how far they meant it should
extend? But if the prince, or whoever they be in the administration, decline that way of
determination, the appeal then lies no where but to heaven; force between either persons,
who have no known superior on earth, or which permits no appeal to a judge on earth, being
properly a state of war, wherein the appeal lies only to heaven; and in that state the
injured party must judge for himself, when he will think fit to make use of that appeal,
and put himself upon it.
|
|
Sec. 243. To conclude, The power that every individual gave
the society, when he entered into it, can never revert to the individuals again, as long
as the society lasts, but will always remain in the community; because without this there
can be no community, no common-wealth, which is contrary to the original agreement: so
also when the society hath placed the legislative in any assembly of men, to continue in
them and their successors, with direction and authority for providing such successors, the
legislative can never revert to the people whilst that government lasts; because having
provided a legislative with power to continue for ever, they have given up their political
power to the legislative, and cannot resume it. But if they have set limits to the
duration of their legislative, and made this supreme power in any person, or assembly,
only temporary; or else, when by the miscarriages of those in authority, it is forfeited;
upon the forfeiture, or at the determination of the time set, it reverts to the society,
and the people have a right to act as supreme, and continue the legislative in themselves;
or erect a new form, or under the old form place it in new hands, as they think good.
|
FINIS. |
|
|