CHAPTER. XVI. |
|
Of Conquest. |
|
|
|
Sec. 175. THOUGH
governments can originally have
no other rise than that before mentioned, nor polities be founded on any thing but the
consent of the people; yet such have been the disorders ambition has filled the world
with, that in the noise of war, which makes so great a part of the history of mankind,
this consent is little taken notice of: and therefore many have mistaken the force of arms
for the consent of the people, and reckon conquest as one of the originals of government.
But conquest is as far from setting up any government, as demolishing an house is from
building a new one in the place. Indeed, it often makes way for a new frame of a
common-wealth, by destroying the former; but, without the consent of the people, can never
erect a new one.
|
|
Sec. 176. That the aggressor, who puts himself into the
state of war with another, and unjustly invades another man's right, can, by such an
unjust war, never come to have a right over the conquered, will be easily agreed by all
men, who will not think, that robbers and pyrates have a right of empire over whomsoever
they have force enough to master; or that men are bound by promises, which unlawful force
extorts from them. Should a robber break into my house, and with a dagger at my throat
make me seal deeds to convey my estate to him, would this give him any title? Just such a
title, by his sword, has an unjust conqueror, who forces me into submission. The injury
and the crime is equal, whether committed by the wearer of a crown, or some petty villain.
The title of the offender, and the number of his followers, make no difference in the
offence, unless it be to aggravate it. The only difference is, great robbers punish little
ones, to keep them in their obedience; but the great ones are rewarded with laurels and
triumphs, because they are too big for the weak hands of justice in this world, and have
the power in their own possession, which should punish offenders. What is my remedy
against a robber, that so broke into my house? Appeal to the law for justice. But perhaps
justice is denied, or I am crippled and cannot stir, robbed and have not the means to do
it. If God has taken away all means of seeking remedy, there is nothing left but patience.
But my son, when able, may seek the relief of the law, which I am denied: he or his son
may renew his appeal, till he recover his right. But the conquered, or their children,
have no court, no arbitrator on earth to appeal to. Then they may appeal, as lephtha did,
to heaven, and repeat their appeal till they have recovered the native right of their
ancestors, which was, to have such a legislative over them, as the majority should
approve, and freely acquiesce in. If it be objected, This would cause endless trouble; I
answer, no more than justice does, where she lies open to all that appeal to her. He that
troubles his neighbour without a cause, is punished for it by the justice of the court he
appeals to: and he that appeals to heaven must be sure he has right on his side; and a
right too that is worth the trouble and cost of the appeal, as he will answer at a
tribunal that cannot be deceived, and will be sure to retribute to every one according to
the mischiefs he hath created to his fellow subjects; that is, any part of mankind: from
whence it is plain, that he that conquers in an unjust war can thereby have no title to
the subjection and obedience of the conquered.
|
|
Sec. 177. But supposing victory favours the right side, let
us consider a conqueror in a lawful war, and see what power he gets, and over whom.
|
|
First, It is plain he gets no power by his conquest over
those that conquered with him. They that fought on his side cannot suffer by the conquest,
but must at least be as much freemen as they were before. And most commonly they serve
upon terms, and on condition to share with their leader, and enjoy a part of the spoil,
and other advantages that attend the conquering sword; or at least have a part of the
subdued country bestowed upon them. And the conquering people are not, I hope, to be
slaves by conquest, and wear their laurels only to shew they are sacrifices to their
leaders triumph. They that found absolute monarchy upon the title of the sword, make their
heroes, who are the founders of such monarchies, arrant Draw-can-sirs, and forget they had
any officers and soldiers that fought on their side in the battles they won, or assisted
them in the subduing, or shared in possessing, the countries they mastered. We are told by
some, that the English monarchy is founded in the Norman conquest, and that our princes
have thereby a title to absolute dominion: which if it were true, (as by the history it
appears otherwise) and that William had a right to make war on this island; yet his
dominion by conquest could reach no farther than to the Saxons and Britons, that were then
inhabitants of this country. The Normans that came with him, and helped to conquer, and
all descended from them, are freemen, and no subjects by conquest; let that give what
dominion it will. And if 1, or any body else, shall claim freedom, as derived from them,
it will be very hard to prove the contrary: and it is plain, the law, that has made no
distinction between the one and the other, intends not there should be any difference in
their freedom or privileges.
|
|
Sec. 178. But supposing, which seldom happens, that the
conquerors and conquered never incorporate into one people, under the same laws and
freedom; let us see next what power a lawful conqueror has over the subdued: and that I
say is purely despotical. He has an absolute power over the lives of those who by an
unjust war have forfeited them; but not over the lives or fortunes of those who engaged
not in the war, nor over the possessions even of those who were actually engaged in it.
|
|
Sec. 179. Secondly, I say then the conqueror gets no power
but only over those who have actually assisted, concurred, or consented to that unjust
force that is used against him: for the people having given to their governors no power to
do an unjust thing, such as is to make an unjust war, (for they never had such a power in
themselves) they ought not to be charged as guilty of the violence and unjustice that is
committed in an unjust war, any farther than they actually abet it; no more than they are
to be thought guilty of any violence or oppression their governors should use upon the
people themselves, or any part of their fellow subjects, they having empowered them no
more to the one than to the other. Conquerors, it is true, seldom trouble themselves to
make the distinction, but they willingly permit the confusion of war to sweep all
together: but yet this alters not the right; for the conquerors power over the lives of
the conquered, being only because they have used force to do, or maintain an injustice, he
can have that power only over those who have concurred in that force; all the rest are
innocent; and he has no more title over the people of that country, who have done him no
injury, and so have made no forfeiture of their lives, than he has over any other, who,
without any injuries or provocations, have lived upon fair terms with him.
|
|
Sec. 180. Thirdly, The power a conqueror gets over those he
overcomes in a just war, is perfectly despotical: he has an absolute power over the lives
of those, who, by putting themselves in a state of war, have forfeited them; but he has
not thereby a right and title to their possessions. This I doubt not, but at first sight
will seem a strange doctrine, it being so quite contrary to the practice of the world;
there being nothing more familiar in speaking of the dominion of countries, than to say
such an one conquered it; as if conquest, without any more ado, conveyed a right of
possession. But when we consider, that the practice of the strong and powerful, how
universal soever it may be, is seldom the rule of right, however it be one part of the
subjection of the conquered, not to argue against the conditions cut out to them by the
conquering sword.
|
|
Sec. 181. Though in all war there be usually a complication
of force and damage, and the aggressor seldom fails to harm the estate, when he uses force
against the persons of those he makes war upon; yet it is the use of force only that puts
a man into the state of war: for whether by force he begins the injury, or else having
quietly, and by fraud, done the injury, he refuses to make reparation, and by force
maintains it, (which is the same thing, as at first to have done it by force) it is the
unjust use of force that makes the war: for he that breaks open my house, and violently
turns me out of doors; or having peaceably got in, by force keeps me out, does in effect
the same thing; supposing we are in such a state, that we have no common judge on earth,
whom I may appeal to, and to whom we are both obliged to submit: for of such I am now
speaking. It is the unjust use of force then, that puts a man into the state of war with
another; and thereby he that is guilty of it makes a forfeiture of his life: for quitting
reason, which is the rule given between man and man, and using force, the way of beasts,
he becomes liable to be destroyed by him he uses force against, as any savage ravenous
beast, that is dangerous to his being.
|
|
Sec. 182. But because the miscarriages of the father are no
faults of the children, and they may be rational and peaceable, notwithstanding the
brutishness and injustice of the father; the father, by his miscarriages and violence, can
forfeit but his own life, but involves not his children in his guilt or destruction. His
goods, which nature, that willeth the preservation of all mankind as much as is possible,
hath made to belong to the children to keep them from perishing, do still continue to
belong to his children: for supposing them not to have joined in the war, either
thro'infancy, absence, or choice, they have done nothing to forfeit them: nor has the
conqueror any right to take them away, by the bare title of having subdued him that by
force attempted his destruction; though perhaps he may have some right to them, to repair
the damages he has sustained by the war, and the defence of his own right; which how far
it reaches to the possessions of the conquered, we shall see by and by. So that he that by
conquest has a right over a man's person to destroy him if he pleases, has not thereby a
right over his estate to possess and enjoy it: for it is the brutal force the aggressor
has used, that gives his adversary a right to take away his life, and destroy him if he
pleases, as a noxious creature; but it is damage sustained that alone gives him title to
another man's goods: for though I may kill a thief that sets on me in the highway, yet I
may not (which seems less) take away his money, and let him go: this would be robbery on
my side. His force, and the state of war he put himself in, made him forfeit his life, but
gave me no title to his goods. The right then of conquest extends only to the lives of
those who joined in the war, not to their estates, but only in order to make reparation
for the damages received, and the charges of the war, and that too with reservation of the
right of the innocent wife and children.
|
|
Sec. 183. Let the conqueror have as much justice on his
side, as could be supposed, he has no right to seize more than the vanquished could
forfeit: his life is at the victor's mercy; and his service and goods he may appropriate,
to make himself reparation; but he cannot take the goods of his wife and children; they
too had a title to the goods he enjoyed, and their shares in the estate he possessed: for
example, I in the state of nature (and all commonwealths are in the state of nature one
with another) have injured another man, and refusing to give satisfaction, it comes to a
state of war, wherein my defending by force what I had gotten unjustly, makes me the
aggressor. I am conquered: my life, it is true, as forfeit, is at mercy, but not my wife's
and children's. They made not the war, nor assisted in it. I could not forfeit their
lives; they were not mine to forfeit. My wife had a share in my estate; that neither could
I forfeit. And my children also, being born of me, had a right to be maintained out of my
labour or substance. Here then is the case: the conqueror has a title to reparation for
damages received, and the children have a title to their father's estate for their
subsistence: for as to the wife's share, whether her own labour, or compact, gave her a
title to it, it is plain, her husband could not forfeit what was her's. What must be done
in the case? I answer; the fundamental law of nature being, that all, as much as may be,
should be preserved, it follows, that if there be not enough fully to satisfy both, viz,
for the conqueror's losses, and children's maintenance, he that hath, and to spare, must
remit something of his full satisfaction, and give way to the pressing and preferable
title of those who are in danger to perish without it.
|
|
Sec. 184. But supposing the charge and damages of the war
are to be made up to the conqueror, to the utmost farthing; and that the children of the
vanquished, spoiled of all their father's goods, are to be left to starve and perish; yet
the satisfying of what shall, on this score, be due to the conqueror, will scarce give him
a title to any country he shall conquer: for the damages of war can scarce amount to the
value of any considerable tract of land, in any part of the world, where all the land is
possessed, and none lies waste. And if I have not taken away the conqueror's land, which,
being vanquished, it is impossible I should; scarce any other spoil I have done him can
amount to the value of mine, supposing it equally cultivated, and of an extent any way
coming near what I had overrun of his. The destruction of a year's product or two (for it
seldom reaches four or five) is the utmost spoil that usually can be done: for as to
money, and such riches and treasure taken away, these are none of nature's goods, they
have but a fantastical imaginary value: nature has put no such upon them: they are of no
more account by her standard, than the wampompeke of the Americans to an European prince,
or the silver money of Europe would have been formerly to an American. And five years
product is not worth the perpetual inheritance of land, where all is possessed, and none
remains waste, to be taken up by him that is disseized: which will be easily granted, if
one do but take away the imaginary value of money, the disproportion being more than
between five and five hundred; though, at the same time, half a year's product is more
worth than the inheritance, where there being more land than the inhabitants possess and
make use of, any one has liberty to make use of the waste: but there conquerors take
little care to possess themselves of the lands of the vanquished, No damage therefore,
that men in the state of nature (as all princes and governments are in reference to one
another) suffer from one another, can give a conqueror power to dispossess the posterity
of the vanquished, and turn them out of that inheritance, which ought to be the possession
of them and their descendants to all generations. The conqueror indeed will be apt to
think himself master: and it is the very condition of the subdued not to be able to
dispute their right. But if that be all, it gives no other title than what bare force
gives to the stronger over the weaker: and, by this reason, he that is strongest will have
a right to whatever he pleases to seize on.
|
|
Sec. 185. Over those then that joined with him in the war,
and over those of the subdued country that opposed him not, and the posterity even of
those that did, the conqueror, even in a just war, hath, by his conquest, no right of
dominion: they are free from any subjection to him, and if their former government be
dissolved, they are at liberty to begin and erect another to themselves.
|
|
Sec. 186. The conqueror, it is true, usually, by the force
he has over them, compels them, with a sword at their breasts, to stoop to his conditions,
and submit to such a government as he pleases to afford them; but the enquiry is, what
right he has to do so? If it be said, they submit by their own consent, then this allows
their own consent to be necessary to give the conqueror a title to rule over them. It
remains only to be considered, whether promises extorted by force, without right, can be
thought consent, and how far they bind. To which I shall say, they bind not at all;
because whatsoever another gets from me by force, I still retain the right of, and he is
obliged presently to restore. He that forces my horse from me, ought presently to restore
him, and I have still a right to retake him. By the same reason, he that forced a promise
from me, ought presently to restore it, i.e. quit me of the obligation of it; or I may
resume it myself, i.e. chuse whether I will perform it: for the law of nature laying an
obligation on me only by the rules she prescribes, cannot oblige me by the violation of
her rules: such is the extorting any thing from me by force. Nor does it at all alter the
case to say, I gave my promise, no more than it excuses the force, and passes the right,
when I put my hand in my pocket, and deliver my purse myself to a thief, who demands it
with a pistol at my breast.
|
|
Sec. 187. From all which it follows, that the government of
a conqueror, imposed by force on the subdued, against whom he had no right of war, or who
joined not in the war against him, where he had right, has no obligation upon them.
|
|
Sec. 188. But let us suppose, that all the men of that
community, being all members of the same body politic, may be taken to have joined in that
unjust war wherein they are subdued, and so their lives are at the mercy of the conqueror.
|
|
Sec. 189. 1 say, this concerns not their children who are in
their minority: for since a father hath not, in himself, a power over the life or liberty
of his child, no act of his can possibly forfeit it. So that the children, whatever may
have happened to the fathers, are freemen, and the absolute power of the conqueror reaches
no farther than the persons of the men that were subdued by him, and dies with them: and
should he govern them as slaves, subjected to his absolute arbitrary power, he has no such
right of dominion over their children. He can have no power over them but by their own
consent, whatever he may drive them to say or do; and he has no lawfull authority, whilst
force, and not choice, compels them to submission.
|
|
Sec. 190. Every man is born with a double right: first, a
right of freedom to his person, which no other man has a power over, but the free disposal
of it lies in himself. Secondly, a right, before any other man, to inherit with his
brethren his father's goods.
|
|
Sec. 191. By the first of these, a man is naturally free
from subjection to any government, tho' he be born in a place under its jurisdiction; but
if he disclaim the lawful government of the country he was born in, he must also quit the
right that belonged to him by the laws of it, and the possessions there descending to him
from his ancestors, if it were a government made by their consent.
|
|
Sec. 192. By the second, the inhabitants of any country, who
are descended, and derive a title to their estates from those who are subdued, and had a
government forced upon them against their free consents, retain a right to the possession
of their ancestors, though they consent not freely to the government, whose hard
conditions were by force imposed on the possessors of that country: for the first
conqueror never having had a title to the land of that country, the people who are the
descendants of, or claim under those who were forced to submit to the yoke of a government
by constraint, have always a right to shake it off, and free themselves from the
usurpation or tyranny which the sword hath brought in upon them, till their rulers put
them under such a frame of government as they willingly and of choice consent to. Who
doubts but the Grecian Christians, descendants of the ancient possessors of that country,
may justly cast off the Turkish yoke, which they have so long groaned under, whenever they
have an opportunity to do it? For no government can have a right to obedience from a
people who have not freely consented to it; which they can never be supposed to do, till
either they are put in a full state of liberty to chuse their government and governors, or
at least till they have such standing laws, to which they have by themselves or their
representatives given their free consent, and also till they are allowed their due
property, which is so to be proprietors of what they have, that no body can take away any
part of it without their own consent, without which, men under any government are not in
the state of freemen, but are direct slaves under the force of war.
|
|
Sec. 193. But granting that the conqueror in a just war has
a right to the estates, as well as power over the persons, of the conquered; which, it is
plain, he hath not: nothing of absolute power will follow from hence, in the continuance
of the government; because the descendants of these being all freemen, if he grants them
estates and possessions to inhabit his country, (without which it would be worth nothing)
whatsoever he grants them, they have, so far as it is granted, property in. The nature
whereof is, that without a man's own consent it cannot be taken from him,
|
|
Sec. 194. Their persons are free by a native right, and
their properties, be they more or less, are their own, and at their own dispose, and not
at his; or else it is no property. Supposing the conqueror gives to one man a thousand
acres, to him and his heirs for ever; to another he lets a thousand acres for his life,
under the rent of 501. or 5001. per arm. has not the one of these a right to his thousand
acres for ever, and the other, during his life, paying the said rent? and hath not the
tenant for life a property in all that he gets over and above his rent, by his labour and
industry during the said term, supposing it be double the rent? Can any one say, the king,
or conqueror, after his grant, may by his power of conqueror take away all, or part of the
land from the heirs of one, or from the other during his life, he paying the rent? or can
he take away from either the goods or money they have got upon the said land, at his
pleasure? If he can, then all free and voluntary contracts cease, and are void in the
world; there needs nothing to dissolve them at any time, but power enough: and all the
grants and promises of men in power are but mockery and collusion: for can there be any
thing more ridiculous than to say, I give you and your's this for ever, and that in the
surest and most solemn way of conveyance can be devised; and yet it is to be understood,
that I have right, if I please, to take it away from you again to morrow?
|
|
Sec. 195. 1 will not dispute now whether princes are exempt
from the laws of their country; but this I am sure, they owe subjection to the laws of God
and nature. No body, no power, can exempt them from the obligations of that eternal law.
Those are so great, and so strong, in the case of promises, that omnipotency itself can be
tied by them. Grants, promises, and oaths, are bonds that hold the Almighty: whatever some
flatterers say to princes of the world, who all together, with all their people joined to
them, are, in comparison of the great God, but as a drop of the bucket, or a dust on the
balance, inconsiderable, nothing!
|
|
Sec. 196. The short of the case in conquest is this: the
conqueror, if he have a just cause, has a despotical right over the persons of all, that
actually aided, and concurred in the war against him, and a right to make up his damage
and cost out of their labour and estates, so he injure not the right of any other. Over
the rest of the people, if there were any that consented not to the war, and over the
children of the captives themselves, or the possessions of either, he has no power; and so
can have, by virtue of conquest, no lawful title himself to dominion over them, or derive
it to his posterity; but is an aggressor, if he attempts upon their properties, and
thereby puts himself in a state of war against them, and has no better a right of
principality, he, nor any of his successors, than Hingar, or Hubba, the Danes, had here in
England; or Spartacus, had he conquered Italy, would have had; which is to have their yoke
cast off, as soon as God shall give those under their subjection courage and opportunity
to do it. Thus, notwithstanding whatever title the kings of Assyria had over Judah, by the
sword, God assisted Hezekiah to throw off the dominion of that conquering empire. And the
lord was with Hezekiah, and he prospered; wherefore he went forth, and he rebelled against
the king of Assyria, and served him not, 2 Kings xviii. 7. Whence it is plain, that
shaking off a power, which force, and not right, hath set over any one, though it hath the
name of rebellion, yet is no offence before God, but is that which he allows and
countenances, though even promises and covenants, when obtained by force, have intervened:
for it is very probable, to any one that reads the story of Ahaz and Hezekiah attentively,
that the Assyrians subdued Ahaz, and deposed him, and made Hezekiah king in his father's
lifetime; and that Hezekiah by agreement had done him homage, and paid him tribute all
this time.
|
|
|